Summary
Hegel moves from the discussion of consciousness in general
to a discussion of self-consciousness. Like the idealist philosophers before
him, Hegel believes that consciousness of objects necessarily implies
some awareness of self, as a subject, which is separate from the
perceived object. But Hegel takes this idea of self-consciousness a
step further and asserts that subjects are also objects to other
subjects. Self-consciousness is thus the awareness of another’s
awareness of oneself. To put it another way, one becomes aware of
oneself by seeing oneself through the eyes of another. Hegel speaks
of the “struggle for recognition” implied in self-consciousness.
This struggle is between two opposing tendencies arising in self-consciousness—between,
on one hand, the moment when the self and the other come together,
which makes self-consciousness possible, and, on the other hand,
the moment of difference arising when one is conscious of the “otherness”
of other selves vis-à-vis oneself, and vice versa. Otherness and
pure self-consciousness are mutually opposed moments in a “life
and death struggle” for recognition. This tension between selves
and others, between mutual identification and estrangement, plays
out in the fields of social relations.
Hegel explains that the realization of self-consciousness
is really a struggle for recognition between two individuals bound
to one another as unequals in a relationship of dependence. One
person is the bondsman and one is the servant. The bondsman, or
servant, is dependent on the lord. Because he is aware that the
lord sees him as an object rather than as a subject (i.e., as a
thing, rather than as a thinking, self-aware being), the lord frustrates
his desire to assert his pure self-consciousness. He is stuck in
a position of reflecting on his otherness. The independent lord,
on the other end, is able to negate the otherness that he finds
reflected through the subordinate bondsman, since the bondsman does
not appear as a conscious subject to him. As the independent and
superior partner in this relationship, his otherness does not bear
down on him. The lord occupies the position of enjoying his dominant
status, whereas the bondsmen must continuously reflect on his status
as a subordinate “other” for the lord. At the same time, the lord
does not find his position completely satisfying. In negating his
own otherness in the consciousness of the bondsman, in turning the
bondsman into an object unessential to his own self-consciousness,
he has also to deny a fundamental impulse toward recognizing the
bondsman as a consciousness equal to himself. At the same time,
the bondsman is able to derive satisfaction in labor, a process
of working on and transforming objects through which he rediscovers
himself and can claim a “mind of his own.”
Analysis
This section of the Phenomenology, and
for that matter the rest of the book, is difficult because of its
abstractness. Hegel writes about lords and bondsmen (or masters
and slaves, as it is sometimes translated), and it is hard at first
to see whom he is talking about and whether this is meant to describe
social relations today or at some period in the past when slavery
was more widespread. Precisely because it is so abstract, the section
has been interpreted in many different ways. It is possible to view
the lord and bondsmen relationship as an early stage of history,
since the Phenomenology describes the evolution
of Spirit throughout the course of human civilization, culminating
in modern society. However, the dialectical evolution of Spirit
throughout history may also be seen as a metaphor for the process
through which each individual develops psychologically. Thus, the
images of the lord and bondsman may be interpreted not literally,
but as metaphors for positions in which we all find ourselves throughout
life—sometimes as the objectified bondsman, sometimes as the objectifying
lord.
The Lordship and Bondage section is among the most widely cited
in all of Hegel’s writings. The struggle for recognition between lord
and bondsman inspired Marx’s account of how class struggle naturally
arises from the exploitation of one social class by another. A diverse
array of twentieth-century thinkers, including psychoanalysts and
existentialists, have drawn on Hegel’s ideas here. Earlier idealists,
such as Kant, pointed out the difference between subject and object,
but Hegel believed that the subject, or the self, is aware of its
self only as a distinct entity through the eyes of another self. The
radical idea inherent in this view is that consciousnesses are inextricably
interwoven and that one cannot have any concept of oneself without
having actually experienced a moment of identification with the
other. Many readers have found his notion of self-consciousness
easier to grasp intuitively than many of Hegel’s other concepts.
His account seems to ring true with everyday experience. People
come to know themselves through the image they suppose others hold
of them. This image is positive or negative depending on who that
person is, where he or she stands in society, and so forth, and
gives rise to familiar stresses as individuals strive to assert
their free individuality against the objectifying images that others
have of them.